Open Journal of Mathematical Analysis

On separability criteria for continuous Bitopological spaces

O. Ogola, N. B. Okelo\(^1\), O. Ongati
Department of Pure and Applied Mathematics, Jaramogi Oginga Odinga University of Science and Technology, Box 210-40601, Bondo-Kenya.; (O.Ogoal & N.B.O & O.Ongati)
\(^{1}\)Corresponding Author: bnyaare@yahoo.com

Abstract

In this paper, we give characterizations of separation criteria for bitopological spaces via \(ij\)-continuity. We show that if a bitopological space is a separation axiom space, then that separation axiom space exhibits both topological and heredity properties. For instance, let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{0}\) space then, the property of \(T_{0}\) is topological and hereditary. Similarly, when \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{1}\) space then the property of \(T_{1}\) is topological and hereditary. Next, we show that separation axiom \(T_{0}\) implies separation axiom \(T_{1}\) which also implies separation axiom \(T_{2}\) and the converse is true.

Keywords:

Bitopological space; Continuous function; ij-Continuity; Separation axiom.

1. Introduction

Studies have been conducted by different authors on continuity and its aspects. Many results have so far been obtained. Most of these results have been successfully obtained by use of separation criteria. This can be done by choosing a topological space that one may wish to use in testing a property of either topological or bitopological space. Separation criteria involve axioms that guide the separation of topological and bitopological spaces. Therefore, separation axioms are restrictions that are often made depending on the kind of topological or bitopological spaces that we intended to consider. Separation axioms involve the use of spaces which distinguish disjoint sets and distinct points. These separation axioms are also called Tychonoff separation axioms.

Fora [1] states that spaces that can be topologically distinguished are said to be separable spaces. Abu-Donia and El-Tantawy [2] conducted a study to show some classes of sets of a bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) which included the infra topologies and supra topologies. These classes introduce new bitopological properties and new types of continuous functions between bitopological spaces. They did some work which indicated that bitopological separation properties are preserved under some types of continuous functions. The properties \(T_{\frac{1}{2}},\) \(T_{b},\) \(\alpha T_{b},\) \(T_{d},\) \(\alpha T_{d}\) are exhibited by topological spaces and finally extended to bitopological spaces. Patil and Nagashree [3] effected some study to show new separation axioms in binary soft topological spaces alongside their properties and characterizations. They have also introduced the notions of binary separation axioms as binary \(T_{0},\) binary \(T_{1},\) binary \(T_{2}\) spaces.

According to [3, Theorem 3.4], every \(n-T^{\ast}_{0}\) is binary soft \(n-T_{0}.\) This result implies that if we have \((x_{1}, y_{1})\) and \((x_{1}, y_{2})\) as two distinct points of a binary soft \(n-T^{\ast}_{0}\) space \((U_{1}, U_{2}, \tau_{b}, E)\) then there exists at least one binary soft open set \((F, E)\) or \((G, E)\) such that \((x_{1}, y_{2})\in (F, E)\), \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in (F, E)\prime\) or \((x_{2}, y_{2}) \in (G, E),\) \((x_{1}, y_{1}) \in (G, E).\) So it implies that \((x_{1}, y_{1})\in (F, E),\) \((x_{2}, y_{2})\) does not exist in \((F, E)\) or \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in (G, E),\) \((x_{1}, y_{1})\) does not exist \((G, E).\) In our study we have considered \(T_{2\frac{1}{2}}\)-spaces as binary soft bitopological space.

According to [3, Theorem 3.11], a binary soft topological space \((U_{1}, U_{2}, \tau_{b}, E)\) is a binary soft \(n-T^{\ast}_{1}\) space if for any pair of distinct points \((x_{1}, y_{1}),\) \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in U_{1} \times U_{2}.\) There exists \((F, E),\) \((G, E)\tau_{b}\) such that \((x_{1}, y_{1})\in (F, E)^{'}\) and \((x_{2}, y_{2}) \in (G, E),\) \((x_{1}, y_{1}) \in (G, E)^{'}.\)

Binary soft property is also seen to be hereditary to some separation axioms as observed in the next result. In [3, Theorem 3.20], it was proved that the property of binary soft \(n-T_{2}\) is hereditary. It illustrates that when \((x_{1}, y_{1})\) \((x_{2}, y_{2})A\times B\) is a pair of distinct points. Then \((x_{1}, y_{1})\), \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in U_{1} \times U_{2}\) are distinct. The fact that \((U_{1}, U_{2}, \tau_{b}, E)\) is binary soft \(n-T_{2}\) there exists disjoint binary soft open sets \((F, E)\) and \((G, E)\) in \((U_{1}, U_{2},\tau_{b}, E)\) such that \((x_{1}, y_{1})\in (F, E)\) and \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in (G, E).\) Therefore, we have disjoint binary soft open sets \(^{Y}(F, E)\) and \(^{Y}(G, E)\) in \((Y, \tau_{bY}, E)\) such that \((x_{1}, y_{1})\in ^{Y}(F, E)\) and also \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in ^{Y}(G, E).\)

Selvanayaki and Rajesh [4] introduced another type of separation axioms in their research of quasi \(T_{\frac{1}{2}^\ast}\) space. A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be quasi \(T_{0}\) if for any two distinct points \(x\) and \(y\) of \(X\) there exists \(A\in QO(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) such that \(x\in X\) where \(y\) does not exists in \(A\) or \(y\in A\) where \(x\) does not exist in \(A.\) A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be \(T_{1}\) if for any distinct points \(x, y\) of \(X\) there exists \(A, B\in QO(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) such that \(x\ A,\) \(y\) does not exist in \(A\) and \(y\in B,\) \(x\) does not exist in \(B.\)

A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be quasi \(T_{2}\) if for any two distinct points \(x, y\) of \(X\) there exists two disjoint sets \(A, B\in QO(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}) = QGC(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) Therefore, it is true that \(T_{2} \rightarrow T_{1} \rightarrow T_{\frac{1}{2}} \rightarrow T_{0}.\) A point \(x\in X\) can be said to be a limit point of a subset \(A\) of a bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\). In [4, Theorem 2.3] it was proved that every quasi \(T_{{\frac{1}{2}^\ast}}\) is quasi \(T_{0}.\)

In our study we are aiming at establishing separation axioms that can be used in aspects of continuity through \(ij\) notion. For a bitopological space \((x, \delta, \tau)\) can be referred to as \(T_{0}\) space if for all \(x, y \in X\) with \(x \neq y\) then there exists in \(\delta \cup \tau\) such that \(x\in U\) whereas \(y\) is not a members of \(U\) on the other hand when \(x\) is not a cardinality of \(U\) then \(y\in U.\) The result is indicated in below: According to [5, Theorem 2.76], a bitopological space \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is called \(T_{1}\) space if for all \(x, y \in X\) with \(x\neq y\) then there exists \(U \in \delta\) and \(V\in \tau\) such that \(x \in U\) where \(y\) does not exists in \( V\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(y \in U.\) In [5, Theorem 2.7], it was proved that a bitopological space \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is called a \(T_{2}\) space if for all \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y\) then there exists \(U\in \delta,\) \(V\in \tau\) such that \(x\in U\) where \(y\in V\) and \(U\cap V=\phi.\)

Rupaya and Hossan [5] have shown some of the results of heredity property exhibited by some separation axioms as given below: In [5, Theorem 3.1], it was proved that if \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a bitopological space then \(T_{0}\) is considered to have hereditary property. This result illustrates that \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is a \(T_{0}\) space and \(A\subset X\) shows that \((A, \delta, \tau)\) is also \(T_{0}\) space. Having \(x, y\in A\) with \(x\neq y\) and \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y.\) Hence if \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is \(T_{0}\) space then there exists \(U \in \delta \cup \tau\) such that \(x\in U\) where \(y\) does not exist in \(U\) or \(x\) also does not exist in \(U\) but \(y\in U\) so \(U\in \delta \cup \tau.\) This imply that \(U\in \delta\) or \(U\in \tau\) then \(U\cap A \in \delta_{A}\) or \(U\cap A \in \tau_{A}.\) Therefore, \(U\cap A \in \delta \cup \tau.\) Then \(x, y \in A\) and \(x\in U\cap A\) where \(y\) does not exist in \(U\cap A\) or \(x\) does not exist in \(U\cap A\) where \(y\in U\cap A.\) Hence \((A, \delta_{A}, \tau_{A})\) is also \(T_{0}.\) Separation axioms also act even on the bitopological spaces that exhibit the homeomorphic property. Homeomorphic image of a particular separation axioms is still that axiom. This has been shown by Rupaya and Hossain [5] in the study of properties of separation axioms in bitopological spaces.

Some result shows that a function \(f:(X, \delta, \tau) \rightarrow (Y, W, Z)\) be a homeomorphism and \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is \(T_{0}\) space. Then \((Y, W, Z)\) can be shown to be a \(T_{0}\) space. This work shows that by letting \(f(X, \delta, \tau)\rightarrow (Y, W, Z)\) to be a homeomorphism and \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is \(T_{1}\) space. Then \((Y, W, Z)\) is also \(T_{1}\) space. Hence \(y_{1}, y_{2}\in Y\) with \(y_{1}\neq y_{2}\). Since \(f\) is onto then there exists \(x_{1}, x_{2} \in X\) with \(f(x_{1})= y_{1}\) and \(f(x_{2}= y_{2}.\) A function \(f\) is one with \(y_{1}\neq y_{2} \rightarrow f(x_{1})\neq f(x_{2})\) this also implies that \(x_{1}\neq x_{2}.\) Then \(x_{1}, x_{2}\in X\) with \(x_{1}\neq x_{2}.\) Again since \((X, \delta, \tau)\) is \(T_{1}\) space then there exists \(U\in \delta\) and \(V\in \tau \) such that \(x_{1}\in U\) and \(x_{2}\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(x_{1}\) does not in \(V\) and \(x_{2}\in V.\) Since \(f\) is open then \(f(U)\in W\) and \(f(V)\in Z.\) In summary, the notion of bitopological spaces was first introduced by Kelly [6] in 1963. Kelly stated that a bitopological space is endowed by two independent topological structures say \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}.\) So a bitopological space that is equipped by two topologies is denoted by \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) A non empty set \(X\) is equipped by two structures \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}.\) By Uryshon's lemma, the results show that existence of quasi-metrics is related to the existence of real-valued functions. Does other properties of bitopological spaces exhibit two topologies a bitopological space?.

In 1984, Ivanov [7] conducted a study on the structures of bitopological spaces. Results obtained show that some properties of a bitopological space as a set \(X\) on which there are given two structures \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) which are defined on the same set as \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) The result was obtained by the use of \(T_{0}\) separation axioms as research methodology. However, from the open question that asks whether all the properties of bitopological spaces inherited by these structures. In 1988, Coy [8] carried out a study on some properties of bitopological spaces such as normality, separability and compactness. Results indicate that they are inherited by a topology in a topological space and as well can be extended to structures in bitopological spaces by the use of conditions of normality and compactness. Does continuity property apply in all spaces?. We consider this question in our study and seek to determine if aspects of continuity can apply to all types of topological spaces. In 2005, Abu-Donia and El-Tantaway [2] gave out generalized separation axioms in bitopological spaces where it was proved that some of the introduced bitopological separation properties are preserved under some types of continuous functions. The extension of semi-continuity, pre-continuity, \(\alpha\)-continuity have also been extended to bitopological space. Does it follow that aspects of continuity can be expressed bilaterally as \(ij\)-continuity in bitopological spaces and N-topological spaces? We consider this question and try to characterize \(ij\)-continuity.

In 2006, Noiri [9] defines semi-open sets and semi-continuity in bitopological spaces. A subset \(A\) of \(X\) is said to be semi-open if it is \((1, 2)\)-semi open and \((2, 1)\)-semiopen. It is also continuous if it is \(ij\)-continuous. Is the continuity determined by all the separation axioms?. We also focus on this question and try to find out if other separation axioms apart from \(T_{0}\) apply. In 2007, Orihuela [10] gave a brief account of topological open problems in the area of renormings of Banach spaces. From question four in open problems, let \(X\) be a weakly Cech analytic Banach space where every norm open set is a countable union of sets which are differences of closed sets for the weak topology. Does it follow that the identity map \(Id : (X, \sigma(X,X^{*})) \rightarrow (X, \| � \|)\) is \(\sigma\)-continuous?. We also consider this question and seek to determine if it holds true when \(X\) is a bitopological space. In 2010, Kohli [11] in the study of between strong and almost continuity gave an account that strong continuity and weak continuity lie strictly between strong continuity of Lavine and strong continuity of Singal. If \(X\) is endowed with a partition topology then, every continuous function \(f: X\rightarrow Y\) is perfectly continuous and hence completely continuous. Is the inverse of a real value function \(f\) continuous?. This question form basis of our research to determine if inverse functions of \(n\)-topologies are also continuous. In 2018, Caldas [12] carried out a study on some topological concepts in bitopological spaces among the concepts given account on are normality, compactness separability among others. From question two in open problems, let function \(f\) be continuous if it maps spaces \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) to \((Y, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) Does most aspects of continuity hold?. We consider this question and try to determine characterization of aspects of continuity.

Birman [13] conducted a study in continuity of bitopological spaces in 2018. Results obtained by using criterion for continuity as research methodology show that most properties including continuity can be induced in a bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) The open question is that can these properties be extended to \(n\)-topological spaces \(A_{1} \cup A_{2} \cup A_{3} \cup ...\cup A_{n}\)?. We also look into possibility of extending properties of bitopological spaces to \(n\)-topologies. Currently in 2019, Rupaya [5] introduced some concepts of separation axioms in bitopological spaces which satisfy topological and hereditary properties. Since a topological space does not imply bitopological space and vice versa. Open question is that do these properties hold in general for both topological and bitopological space?.

In this paper we characterize separability criteria for bitopological spaces.

2. Preliminaries

In this section, we outline the basic concepts which are useful in the sequel.

Definition 1. [14, Definition 1.1.1] Let \(X\) be a nonempty set. A collection of subsets of \(X\) denoted by \(\tau\) is said to be a topology on \(X\) if and only if the following properties are satisfied:

  • (i). \(X\) and \(\emptyset\) belong to \(\tau.\)
  • (ii). Any arbitrary union of members of \(\tau\) belongs to \(\tau.\)
  • (iii). Any finite intersection of any two members of \(\tau\) belongs to \(\tau.\)
The ordered pair \((X, \tau)\) is called a topological space.

Definition 2. [15, Definition 2.1] Let \(X\) be a nonempty set and \(\tau_{1},\) \(\tau_{2}\) be topologies on \(X.\) Then \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be a bitopological space.

Definition 3. [16, Definition 1.7] Let \((X, \tau)\) be a topological space and \((Y, \tau_{X})\) be a subspace of \(X\) which is equipped with a topology induced or inherited from that of \(X.\)

Definition 4.[17, Definition 2.4] Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}, E)\) be a soft bitopological space over \(X\) and \(Y\) be a nonempty subset of \(X.\) Then \(\tau_{1Y} = \{(Y, F, E): (F, E)\in \tau_{1}\}\) and \(\tau_{2Y} = \{(Y, G, E) \in \tau_{2}\}\) are said to be relatively topologies on \(Y.\) Therefore, \(\{Y, \tau_{1Y}, \tau_{2Y}, E\}\) is called a relatively soft bitopological space of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\)

Example 1. [18, Example 1.1.2] Let \(X = \{a, b, c\}.\) Let the collection of subsets of \(X\) is denoted by topology \(\tau.\) Then \(\tau = \{\{a\}, \{b\}, \{c\},\{a,b\}, \{b, c\}, \{a, c\}, \{X\}, \emptyset\}.\) Then \(\tau\) is a topology on \(X\) if it satisfies conditions (i), (ii) and (iii) in Definition 1.

For condition (i) both \(X\) and \(\phi\) are in \(\tau.\)

For condition (ii) \(\{ a, c\} \cup \{ b,c\} = \{ a, b, c \} = X,\) which is a member of \(\tau.\)

For condition (iii) \(\{a\} \cap \{a, c\} = \{a\},\) which is a member of \(\tau.\)

Definition 5.[19, Definition 2.4] A mapping \(f: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (X_{1}, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is called \(P\)-continuous (respectively open, \(P\)-closed) if the induced mapping \(f:( X, \tau_{1})\rightarrow (X_{1}, \tau_{3})\) and \(f: (X, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (X_{1}, \tau_{4})\) are continuous (respectively open, closed).

Definition 6. [20, Definition 4.1] Let \(X\) and \(Y\) be \(N\)-topological space. A function \(f: X\rightarrow Y\) is said to be \(N^{\ast}\)-continuous on \(X\) if the inverse image of every \(N\tau\)-open set in \(Y\) is a \(N\tau\)-open set in \(X.\)

Definition 7. [5, Definition 2.5] A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is called \(T_{0}\) space if \(\forall\) \(x, y \in X\) with \(x\neq y.\) Then there exists \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exists in \(U\) or \(x\) does not exists in \(Y,\) \(y\in U.\)

Example 2.[14, Example 4.1.2] Consider \(X = \{a, b, c, e, f\}\), \(Y=\{b, c, e\}\) and \(\tau = \{ X, \phi, \{a\}, \{c, d\}, \{a, c, d\}, \{b, c, d, e, f\}\}\) and \(Y = \{b, c,e\}.\) Therefore, \((Y, \tau)\) is a subspace of \((X, \tau).\) Since topology \(\tau\) on \(Y\) is induced from \(X\) then all properties of a topological space \((X, \tau)\) has are also in a subspace \((Y, \tau).\) This subspace is denoted as \(\tau_{Y} = Y \mid \tau _{X}.\)

Definition 8.[6, Definition 1.2] A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a space that is endowed with two independent topologies say \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) denoted as \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\)

Example 3. [21, Example 3.2] Let \(X=\{a, b,\}, \tau=\{\emptyset, \{a\}, \{c\}, \{a, c\}, X\}\) and \(\tau_{\beta}=\{\emptyset, X, \{a\}, \{c\}, \{a, c\},\\ \{b, c\}, \{a, b\}\}\) then \(\{a, c\}\) is connected.

Definition 9.[5, Definition 2.6] A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is called \(T_{1}\) space if \(\forall\) \(x, y \in X\) with \(x\ne y.\) Then there exists \(U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(y\in U.\)

Example 4.[19, Example 1] Consider \(X=\{a, b, c\}\) with topologies \(P=\{\emptyset, \{b\}, \{c\}, \{b, c\}, X\}\) and \(Q=\emptyset, \{a\}, \{b\}, \{a, b\}, \{b, c\}, x\}\) defined on \(X.\) Therefore, \(P\)-closed subsets of \(X\) are \(\emptyset, \{a, c\}, \{a, b\}, \{a\}\) and \(X\). \(Q\)-closed subsets of \(X\) are \(\emptyset, \{b, c\}, \{a, c\}, \{c\}, \{a\}\) and \(X.\) It follows that \((X, P, Q)\) does satisfy the condition \(P\)-normal. Hence \((X, P, Q)\) is \(P\)-normal.

Definition 10.[22, Definition 3.19] A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be:

  • (i). Pairwise \(S\)-closed if every pairwise regular, pairwise closed cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) has a finite subcover.
  • (ii). Pairwise \(S\)-closed if every pairwise countable cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) by pairwise regular closed sets with respect to \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) has a finite subcover.
  • (iii). Pairwise \(S\)-Lindelof if every pairwise cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) by pairwise regular closed sets with respect to \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) has a finite pairwise countable subcover.
  • (iv). Nearly pairwise compact if every pairwise regular open cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) has a finite subcover.
  • (v). Pairwise countably nearly pairwise compact if every pairwise countable cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) by pairwise regular open sets with respect to \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) has a finite subcover.
  • (vi). Nearly pairwise Lindelof if every pairwise regular open cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) has a pairwise countable subcover.

Definition 11.[23, Definition 3.14] Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) and \((Y, \sigma_{1}, \sigma_{2})\) be two bitopological spaces. A function \(f: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \sigma_{1}, \sigma_{2})\) is called \((1, 2)-\gamma\) semi-continuous if the inverse image of each \(\sigma_{1}\)-open set in \(Y\) is \((1, 2)-\gamma\) -semi-open set in \(X.\)

Remark 1.[24, Remark 5] Each of \(ij\)-irresoluteness \(ij\)-almost \(s\)-continuity and \(i\)-continuity is independent of one another and \(ij\)-almost \(s\)-continuity is not a generalization of \(i\)-continuity. Each of \(ij\)-quasi irresoluteness \(ij\)-semi-continuity and \(ij\)-almost continuity is independent of one another.

Definition 12.[25, Definition 2.1] A function \(f:X\rightarrow Y\) from a topological space \(X\) to A topological space \(Y\) is said to be:

  • (i). Strongly continuous if \(f (\overline{A}) \subset A\) for all \(A \subset X.\)
  • (ii). Perfectly continuous if \(f^{-1}(V)\) is clopen in \(X\) for every open set \(V\subset Y.\)
  • (iii). \(\sigma\)-perfectly continuous if for each \(\sigma\)-open set \(V\) in \(Y\), \(f^{-1}(V)\) is a clopen set.

Definition 13.[26, Definition 1.4.1] A function \(f\) is continuous at some point \(x\in X\) if and only if for any neighborhood \(V\) of \(f(X)\) hence there is a neighborhood \(U\) of \(x\) such that \(f(U)\subseteq V.\)

Definition 14.[11, Definition 3.2] Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a topological space and \(N\) be a subset of \(X\) and \(p\) a point in \(N.\) Then \(N\) is said to be a neighborhood of the point \(p\) if there exists an open set \(U\) such that \(p\in U\subseteq N.\)

Example 5.[27, Example 2.3] Let \(X=\{1, 2, 3\}\), \(P=\{\emptyset, X, \{1, 2\}, \{3\}\}\) and \(Q=\{\emptyset, X, \{1\}, \{2, 3\}\}\). It is easy to check that \((X, P, Q)\) is pairwise \(T_{0}\) but not weak pairwise \(T_{1}\) considering the points 1, 2.

Definition 15.[28, Definition 2] The intersection (resp. union) of all (i, j) -\(\delta\)-closed (resp. (i, j)-\(\delta\)-open sets \(X\) containing (resp. contained in) \(A\subset X\) is called the \((i, j)-\delta\)-closure (resp. \((i, j)-\delta\)-interior of an \(A.\)

Definition 16.[29, Definition 3] A subset of a bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be (i, j)-\(\delta\)-b-open. If \(A\subset j Cl (i Int-{\delta} (A))\cup i Int(j Cl_{\delta} (A))\), where \(i \neq j i, j =1, 2.\) The complement of an \((i, j)-\delta-b\)-open set is called an \((i, j)-\delta- b\)-closed set.

Example 6. [30, Example 7] Suppose that intersection (resp.union) for all \((i, j)-\delta-b\)-closed \((resp. (i, j)-\delta-b\)-open) sets of \(X\) containing (resp. contained in) \(A\subset X\) is called the \((i, j)-\delta-b\)-closure \((resp. (i, j)-\delta-b\)-interior) of \(A\) and is denoted by \((i, j)-b Cl_{\delta} (A) (resp. (i, j)-b Int_{\delta} (A))\) The intersection of all \((i, j) -b-\delta\)-open sets of \(X\) containing \(A\) is called \((i, j)-b-\delta\)-kernel of \(A\) and is denoted by \((i, j)-b Ker_{\delta}(A).\)

Example 7.[19, Example 2] Consider \(X=\{a, b, c, d\}\) with topologies \(P=\{\emptyset, \{a, b\}, X\}\) and \(Q=\{\emptyset, \{a\}, \{b, c, d\}, X\}\) defined on \(X.\) Observe that \(P\)-closed subsets of \(X\) are \(\emptyset, \{c, d\}\) and \(X.\) \(Q\)-closed subsets of \(X\) are \(\emptyset, \{b, c, d\}, \{a\}\) and \(X.\) Hence \((X, P, Q)\) is \(P1\)-normal as we can check since the only pairwise closed sets of \(X\) are \(\emptyset\) and \(X.\) However, \((X, P, Q)\) is not \(P\)-normal since the \(P\)-closed set \(A=\{c, d\}\) and \(Q\)-closed set \(B=\{a\}\) satisfy \(A\cap B=\emptyset\) but do not exists the \(Q\)-open set \(U\) and \(P\)-open set \(V\) such that \(A\subseteq U, B\subseteq V\) and \(U\cup V=\emptyset.\)

Definition 17.[31, Definition 4.2] A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be pairwise \(R_{0}\) if for every \(T_{i}\)-open set \(G\), \(x\in G\) implies \(T_{i}-cl\{x\}\subset G\) i,j = 1, 2, \(i\neq j.\)

Remark 2.[24, Remark 1] Every \(ij\)-regular open set is \(ji\) semiregular.

Definition 18.[32, Definition 4.3] A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be pairwise \(R_{0}\) if for every \(T_{i}\)-open set \(G,\) \(x\in G\) implies that \(T_{j}-\delta cl \{x\}\subset G\), i, j = 1, 2, \(i\neq j.\)

Example 8. [33, Example 3.12] Let \(X=\{a, b, c\},\) \(\tau_{1}=\{X, \emptyset, \{a\}\}\) and \(\tau_{2}=\{X, \emptyset, \{a\}, \{a, b\}, \{a, c\}\}.\) Clearly, \((X, \tau_{1})=(X, \tau_{2})=(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})= \tau_{2}.\) Thus \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a a quasi-\(b-T_\frac{1}{2}\) space that is not quasi-\(b-T_{1}.\)

Definition 19.[19, Definition 3.6] A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is called:

  • (i). Pairwise pre-\(T_{0}\) (resp. pairwise pre-\(T_{1}\)) if for any pair of distinct points \(x\) and \(y\) in \(X,\) there exists a \(T_{i}\)-preopen set which contains one of them but not the other \(i= 1\) or \(2\) resp. there exists \(T_{i}\)-preopen set \(U\) and \(T_{j}\)-preopen set \(V\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\in V\) and \(U\cap V = \emptyset i, j =1, 2 , i\neq j.\)
  • (ii). A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be pairwise pre-\(T_{2}\) if for any pair of distinct points \(x\) and \(y\) in \(X,\) there exists \(\tau_{i}\)-preopen set \(U\) and \(\tau_{j}\)-preopen set \(V\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\in V\) and \(U\cap V \neq \emptyset\) i, j= 1, 2, where \(i\neq j.\)

Example 9.[34, Example 2] Let \(X=\{a, b, c, d, e\}, \tau_{1}=\{\emptyset, X\}, \tau_{2}=\{\emptyset, X, \{b, e\}\},\) \( Y=\{a, b, c, d\}, \sigma_{1}=\{\emptyset, Y, \{c\}\}\) and \(\sigma_{2}=\{\emptyset, Y, \{b, d\}\}.\) Suppose \(f:(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \sigma_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is defined by \(f(a)=f(c)=f(d), f(b)=f(c), f(b)=f(e)=b.\) Then the map \(f\) is \(12\)-preweak continuous but not \(12\)-preweak semicontinuous since \(f^{-1}(\{c\})=\{a, c, d\}\) which is not 1-open set in the subspace \(2-cl(1-int(2-cl(f^{-1}(2-cl(\{c\}))))).\)

Definition 20. [35, Definition 3.19] A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be:

  • (i). Pairwise \(S\)-closed if every pairwise regular, pairwise closed cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) has a finite subcover.
  • (ii). Pairwise \(S\)-closed if every pairwise countable cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) by pairwise regular closed sets with respect to \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) has a finite subcover.
  • (iii). Pairwise \(S\)-Lindelöf if every pairwise cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) by pairwise regular closed sets with respect to \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) has a finite pairwise countable subcover.
  • (iv). Nearly pairwise compact if every pairwise regular open cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) has a finite subcover.
  • (v). Pairwise countably nearly pairwise compact if every pairwise countable cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) by pairwise regular open sets with respect to \(\tau_{1}\) and \(\tau_{2}\) has a finite subcover.
  • (vi). Nearly pairwise Lindelöf if every pairwise regular open cover of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) has a pairwise countable subcover.

Definition 21.[36, Definition 3.1] Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a bitopological space. Then, we say that a subset \(A\) of \(X\) is \(\tau_{1}\) semi open with respect to \(\tau_{2}\) if and only if there exists a \(\tau_{2}\) open set \(O\) such that \(O \subset A\subset \tau_{2}\) closure \(O.\)

Definition 22.[37, Definition 2.4] The quasi \(b\)-closure of a subset \(A\) of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is defined to be \(qbCl(A)=\cap {F: F\in QBC(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}), A\subseteq F}.\) A subset \(A\) of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi-b-generalized closed (simply, quasi-bg-closed) if \(qbCl(A)\subseteq U.\)

Definition 23.[38, Definition 2.3] A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is said to be \(i\)-Lindelöf if both the topological space \((X, \tau_{i})\) is Lindeloöf. \(X\) is called Lindelöf if it is both 1-Lindelöf and 2-Lindelöf. Equivalently, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is Lindelöf if every \(i\)-open cover of \(X\) has a countable subcover for each \(i = 1, 2\).

Definition 24.[17, Definition 5] The union of two soft sets of \((F, A)\) and \((G, B)\) over the common universe \(U\) is the soft set \((H, C)\), where \(C= A\cup B\) and for all \(e\in E.\) This can be denoted as \((F, A) \cup (G, B)= (H, C).\)

Example 10.[4, Definition 3.1] A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi-\(b-T_{0}\) if for every two distinct points \(x, y\) of \(X\), there exists \(A\in QBO(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) such that \(x \in A\) and \(y\) not in \(A\) or \(x\) not in \(A\) and \(y\in A.\)

Definition 25. [3, Definition 3.2] A binary soft topological space \((U_{1}, U_{2}, \tau_{b}, E)\) is said to be binary soft \(n-T_{0}\) if for any pair \((x_{1}, y_{1})\), \((x_{1}, y_{2})\in U_{1} \times U_{2}\) of distinct points that is, \(x_{1}\neq x_{2}\) and \(y_{1} \neq y_{2}\) there exists at least one binary soft open set \((F, E)\) or \((G, E)\) such that \((x_{1}, y_{1})\in (F, E)\), \((x_{2}, y_{2})\) does not exists in \((G, E)\) or \((x_{2}, y_{2})\in (G, E)\) and \((x_{1}, y_{1})\) does not exists in \((G, E).\)

Definition 26. [33, Definition 3.4] A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi-\(b-T_{2}\) if for every two distinct points \(X,\) \(y\) of \(X,\) there exists disjoint sets \(A, B\in QBO(X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) such that \(x\in A\) and \(y\in B.\)

Definition 27. [17, Definition 3] The intersection \((H, C)\) of two sets \((F, A)\) and \((G, B)\) over a common universe \(U\). Denoted as \((F, A)\cap (G, B)\), is defined as \(C= A\cap B.\) Also \(H(e)= F(e)\cap G(e)\) for all \(e\in C.\)

Definition 28. [39, Definition 4.5] A space \(X\) is normal on a subset \(Y.\) Then if every two disjoint closed subsets \(F\) and \(G\) of \(X\) satisfying \(F=\overline{F \cap Y}\) and \(G=\overline{G \cap Y}\) can be separated in \(X\) by disjoint open sets. Suppose that we have a separable space \(X\) then the following conditions are equivalent:

  • (i). \(X\) is said to be normal on every dense countable subset.
  • (ii). Any two separable disjoint subspaces if \(X\) can be represented by disjoint open set.

Remark 3. [40, Definition 2.1] A bitopological space \((X, P, Q)\) is weak pairwise \(T_{0}\) if and only if each pair of distinct points, there is a set which is either \(p\)-open or \(q\)-open containing one but not the other.

Definition 29.[4, Definition 3.1] Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a topological space and \(A\subset X.\) Then \(A\) is said to be weakly quasi separated from set \(B\) if there exists a quasi open set \(G\) such that \(A\subset G\) and \(G\cap B=\emptyset\) or \(A\cap qcl(B)=\emptyset.\)

Definition 30. [41, Definition 2.2] Let \(U_{1},\) \(U_{2}\) be two initial universe sets with powers \(P(U_{1})\) and \(P(U_{2})\) respectively and \(E\) be a set of parameters. A pair \((F, E)\) is said to be a binary soft set over \(U_{1}\) and \(U_{2}\) where \(F\) is defined as \(F: E\rightarrow P(U_{1}) \times P(U_{2}),\) \(F(e)= (X, Y)\) for each \(e\in E\) such that \(X\subset U_{1},\) \(Y\subset U_{2}.\)

3. Main results

Proposition 1. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{0}\) space then the property of \(T_{0}\) is hereditary and topological.

Proof. We prove that \(T_{0}\) has hereditary property. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{0}\) space and let \(D\subseteq X.\) Then we show that a bitopological subspace \((D, \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) is also a \(T_{0}\) space. Since \((D,s \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) has induced properties from \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) then it implies that \(a, b\in D\) with \(a\neq b,\) then \(a, b\in X\) with \(a \neq b\) as in Definition 7. Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{0}\) space then \(\exists U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(a\in U,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\) or \(a\) is not a member of \(U\) but \(b\in U.\) Then it follows that \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(U\in \tau_{1}\) or \(U\in \tau_{2}.\) Therefore, \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D1}\) or \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D2}\) and so \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D1} \cap \tau_{D2}.\) Again since \(a, b\in D\) then \(a\in U\cap D,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\cap D\) or \(a\) does not exists in \(U\cap D,\) and \(b\in U\cap D.\) Hence \((D, \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) is also a \(T_{0}\) space. Secondly, we prove that \(T_{0}\) has topological property. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) be a homeomorphism and let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{0}\) space we therefore show that \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is also a \(T_{0}\) space. By Definition, \(\chi:(X, \tau_{1})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3})\) and \(\chi: (X, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{4})\) are continuous (open, closed, homeomorphism respectively). Let \(b_{1}, b_{2} \in Y\) with \(b_{1}\neq b_{2},\) since \(\chi\) is an onto function then \(\exists a_{1}, a_{2}\in X\) with \(\chi (a_{1}) = \chi(b_{1})\) and \(\chi(a_{2}) = b_{2}\) as Definition 5. Since \(\chi\) is an injective function with \(b_{1} \neq b_{2}\) therefore it implies that \(\chi(a_{1}) \neq \chi(a_{2})\) hence \(a_{1} \neq a_{2}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(T_{0}\) space and \(a_{1}, a_{2}\in X\) where \(a_{1} \neq a_{2}\) then it implies that there exists \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(a_{1}\in U,\) \(a_{1}\) does not exists in \(U\) or \(a_{1}\) does not exists in \(U,\) \(a_{2}\in U\) or \(a_{1}\in U,\) \(a_{2}\) does not exists in \(U.\) Then \(U\in \tau_{1}\cup \tau_{2}\) follows that \(\chi (U)\in \chi(\tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2})\) since \(\chi\) is open and continuous. By Tychonoff separation axiom, it implies that \(\chi (U)\in\chi(\tau_{1})\cup\chi(\tau_{2})\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}.\) Also \(a_{1}\in U\) which implies that \(\chi(a_{1})\in \chi (U)\) or \(b_{1}\in \chi(U)\) and \(a_{2}\) does not exists in \(U\) which imply that \(\chi(a_{2})\) does not exists in \(\chi(U)\) or \(b_{2}\) does not exists \(\chi(U).\) For any \(b_{1}, b_{2}\in Y\) with \(b_{1} \neq b_{2},\) \(\chi(U)\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}\) is obtained such that \(b_{1}\in \chi (U),\) \(b_{2}\) does not exists in \(\chi(U).\) Therefore, \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is a \(T_{0}\) space. Every homeomorphic image of \(T_{0}\) space implies that it is topological property.

Proposition 2. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{1}\) space then the property of \(T_{1}\) is topological and hereditary.

Proof. Suppose that \(T_{1}\) has hereditary property then \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is also \(T_{1}\) space. Let \(D\subseteq X\) and hence \((D, \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) is also \(T_{1}\) space. Let \(a, b\in D\) with \(a\neq b\) and \(a, b\in X\) with \(a \neq b.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{1}\) space then \(\exists U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(a\in U,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(a\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(b\in U.\) By Proposition 1, we have \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}.\) Then \(U\in \tau_{1}\) or \(U\in \tau_{2}\) with \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D1}\) or \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D2}\) also \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D1} \cap \tau_{D2}.\) Since \(a, b\in D\) hence \(a\in U\cap D,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\cap D\) or \(a\) does not exists in \(U\cap D,\) \(b\in U\cap D.\) Therefore, \((D, \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) is also a \(T_{1}\) space. Secondly, we show that \(T_{1}\) space has a topological property. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) be a homeomorphism and \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be \(T_{0}\) space. Then by hypothesis \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is a \(T_{1}\) space. Let \(b_{1}, b_{2} \in Y\) where \(b_{1}\neq b_{2}.\) Suppose that \(\chi\) is surjective then it follows that there exists \(a_{1}, a_{2}\in X\) with \(\chi (a_{1}) = \chi(b_{1})\) and \(\chi(a_{2}) = b_{2}.\) Hence \(\chi\) is also one to one function with \(b_{1} \neq b_{2}\) this implies that \(\chi(a_{1}) \neq \chi(a_{2})\) hence \(a_{1} \neq a_{2}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{1}\) space and \(a_{1}, a_{2}\in X,\) with \(a_{1} \neq a_{2}.\) Then \(\exists U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(a_{1}\in U,\) \(a_{1}\) does not exists in \(U\) or \(a_{1}\) does not exists in \(U,\) \(a_{2}\in U.\) Since \(a_{1}\in U,\) \(a_{2}\) does not exists in \(U\) then it implies that \(U\in \tau_{1}\cup\tau_{2}.\) Therefore, \(\chi (U)\in \chi(\tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}).\) By Tychonoff Theorem, \(\chi\) is open and continuous then \(\chi (U)\in\chi(\tau_{1})\cup\chi(\tau_{2})\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}.\) Similarly, \(a_{1}\in U\) hence it follows that \(\chi(a_{1})\in \chi (U)\) also \(b_{1}\in \chi(U)\) and \(a_{2}\) does not exists in \(U\) which implies that \(\chi(a_{2})\) does not exists in \(\chi(U),\) and so \(b_{2}\) does not exists \(\chi(U).\) Then for any \(b_{1}, b_{2}\in Y\) with \(b_{1} \neq b_{2}\) and \(\chi(U)\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}\) is obtained such that \(b_{1}\in \chi (U),\) \(b_{2}\) does not exists in \(\chi(U).\) Therefore, \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is also a \(T_{1}\) space. Hence \(\chi\) is continuous (open, closed and homeomorphism) if and only if the maps \(\chi:(X, \tau_{1})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3})\) and \(\chi: (X, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{4})\) are continuous (open, closed and homeomorphism respectively). By hypothesis, every homeomorphism image of \(T_{1}\) space imply \(T_{0}\) space. Therefore, a \(T_{1}\) space is a topological property.

Proposition 3. Suppose that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space then the property of \(T_{2}\) is topological and hereditary.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) and \((Y, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be two bitopological spaces. If \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space then it exhibits topological properties. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) be a homeomorphism and \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is also a \(T_{2}\) space. Then we show that \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is also \(T_{2}\) space. By Definition 27, let \(b_{1}, b_{2}\in Y\) with \(y_{1} \neq y_{2}\). Since all elements in \(Y\) are images of elements in \(X\) then \(\chi\) is a surjective function. Then there exists \(a_{1} ,a_{2} \in X\) with \(\chi (a_{1}) = b_{1}\) and \(\chi(a_{2}) = b_{2}.\) Again since \(\chi\) is an injective function then \(b_{1} \neq b_{2}.\) This implies that \(\chi(a_{1}) \neq \chi(a_{2}),\) and \(a_{1} \neq a_{2}.\) Therefore, \(a_{1}, a_{2} \in X\) with \(a_{1} \neq a_{2}.\) Consequently, since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space then it shows that \(\exists U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(a_{1}\in U,\) \(a_{2}\in V\) then \(U\cap V\neq \emptyset.\) Suppose that \(\chi\) is open then \(\chi(U)\in \tau_{3}\) and \(\chi (V)\in \tau_{4}.\) Therefore, \(\chi(U)\cap \chi(V)\neq \emptyset\) then there exists \(c\in X\) such that \(c\in \chi(U) \cap \chi(V).\) This shows that \(c\in \chi(U)\) and \(c\in \chi(V)\) then \(\exists p_{1}\in U\) and \(p_{2}\in V\) such that \(c= \chi(p_{1})\) and \(c\in \chi(p_{2})\) with \(\chi(p_{1}) = \chi(p_{2})\) and \(p_{1}= p_{2}\) since \(\chi\) is a one to one function and so \(p_{1}\in U\) and \(p_{1}\in V.\) hence \(p_{1}\in U\cap V\neq \emptyset\) which is by contradiction. Suppose that \(U\cap V= \emptyset\) which implies that \(\chi(U) \cap \chi(V)=\emptyset.\) Therefore, for any \(b_{1}, b_{2}\in Y\) with \(b_{1} \neq b_{2}\) hence \(\chi(U) =\tau_{3}\) and \(\chi (V)\in c\) is obtained such that \(b_{1} \in \chi(U),\) \(b_{2} \in \chi(V)\) and so \(\chi(U) \cap \chi(V)\neq \emptyset.\) Hence \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space. So it implies that every homeomorphism image of a \(T_{2}\) is a \(T_{2}\) space. Then \(T_{2}\) is a topological property. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{2}\) space then it has hereditary property. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) also be \(T_{2}\) space. Since \(D\subseteq X,\) we prove that \((D, \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) is also \(T_{2}\) space. Let \(a, b\in D\) with \(a\neq b\) and \(a, b\in X\) and also \(a \neq b.\) By Definition 9, it follows that \(\exists U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(a\in U,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\) and also \(a\) does not exists in \(U\) but \(b\in U.\) So \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2},\) it implies that \(U\in \tau_{1}\) or \(U\in \tau_{2}\) where \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D1}\) or \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D2}.\) By Tychonoff theorem, \(U\cap D\in \tau_{D1} \cap \tau_{D2}.\) Again since \(a, b\in D\) then \(a\in U\cap D,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\cap D\) or \(a\) does not exists in \(U\cap D\), \(b\in U\cap D.\) Therefore, \((D, \tau_{D1}, \tau_{D2})\) is also a \(T_{2}\) space and has a topological property.

Proposition 4. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space then the property of \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) is topological and hereditary.

Proof. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4}).\) By hypothesis, \(T_{1}\) space imply \(T_{2}\) space which also implies \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. Therefore, we prove that \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space has hereditary property. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space and let \(K\subseteq X.\) Then \((K, \tau_{K1}, \tau_{K2})\) is a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space since it is bitopological subspace of \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) Then it implies that \((K, \tau_{K1}, \tau_{K2})\) is a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. Let \(m, n\in K\) with \(m\neq n\) then if \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space then \(\exists A\in \tau_{1}\) and \(B\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(m\in A,\) \(n\in B\) such that the intersection of \(A\) and \(B\) is empty that is, \(A\cap B = \emptyset.\) Hence \(A\in \tau_{1},\) \(B\in \tau_{2}\) then it follows that \(A\cap K\in \tau_{K1}\) and \(B\cap K\in \tau_{K2}.\) Therefore, \(m, n\in K\) then \(m\in A\cap K\), \(n\in B\cap K.\) So \((A\cap K)\cap (B\cap K)= (A\cap K)\cap K=\emptyset \cap K=\emptyset,\) hence \((K, \tau_{K1}, \tau_{K2})\) is \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. Then \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is also a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space so it also has a topological property. By hypothesis \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) and \(\chi\) is a homeomorphic function then it follows that \((Y,\tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is also a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. Therefore, \(n_{1}, n_{2} \in Y\) with \(n_{1}\neq n_{2}.\) Since \(\chi\) is onto function then it implies that \(\exists m_{1}, m_{2}\in X\) with \(\chi (m_{1}) = \chi(n_{1})\) and \(\chi(m_{2}) = n_{2}.\) Suppose \(\chi\) is injective with \(n_{1} \neq n_{2}\) then it implies that \(\chi(m_{1}) \neq \chi(m_{2})\) and so \(m_{1} \neq m_{2}.\) Hence \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space then \(m_{1}, m_{2}\in X,\) with \(m_{1} \neq m_{2}\) and \(\exists A\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(m_{1}\in A,\) \(m_{1}\) does not exists in \(A\) or \(m_{1}\) does not exists in \(A,\) \(a_{2}\in A.\) Similarly, \(m_{1}\in A\), \(m_{2}\) does not exists in \(U\) therefore it implies that \(A\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(\chi (A)\in \chi(\tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}).\) By condition for separation axioms, \(\chi (A) \in \chi(\tau_{1}) \cup \chi(\tau_{2})\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4},\) \(m_{1}\in A\) such that \(\chi(m_{1})\in \chi (A)\) hence \(n_{1}\in \chi(A)\) and \(m_{2}\) does not exists in \(A\) and \(\chi(m_{2})\) does not exists in \(\chi(A)\), this implies that \(n_{2}\) does not exists \(\chi(A)\) for any \(n_{1}, n_{2}\in Y\) with \(n_{1} \neq n_{2},\) \(\chi(A)\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}\) is obtained such that \(n_{1}\in \chi (A),\) \(n_{2}\) does not exists in \(\chi(A).\) Therefore, \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is also \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. Each homeomorphic image of \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space is also \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space and hence it has topological property.

Lemma 1. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a normal space then the property of normality imply topological and hereditary.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a normal bitopological space. Then there exist two disjoint closed sets \(x\) and \(y\) with \(x\neq y\) and two disjoint open sets say \(U\) and \(V\) such that \(x\subset U\) and \(y\subset V.\) By Definition, two disjoint closed sets \(x, y \in X\) this therefore implies that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(y\in V.\) Since normal bitopological space implies \(T_{2}\) space then we have \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y\) then \(\exists U\in \tau_{1}\cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exists in \(U\) and also \(x\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(y\in V\) therefore normal spaces have topological property. Secondly, we prove that normality imply hereditary property. By Proposition 2, \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) and \(\chi\) is homeomorphism if and only if it is a bijective function. Let \(A\subseteq X\) and let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a normal space then this implies that \(A\) is also normal. By conditions for normality, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a normal space then \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is also normal since disjoints closed sets \(x,y\in A\) and \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y.\) Therefore, considering disjoint open sets \(U\) and \(V\) we have \(U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\in V\) and \(U\cap V=\emptyset.\) Therefore, \(U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) then it implies that \(U\cap A\in \tau_{A1}\) and \(V\cap A\in \tau_{A2}\) hence it follows that \(x\in \cap AU\), \(y\in V\cap A.\) Then it implies that \((U\cap A) \cap (V\cap A) \cap A = \emptyset \cap A = \emptyset.\) By hypothesis, \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is normal and has topological property induced from \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\)

Proposition 5. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\) if and only if it is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-symmetric.

Proof. Assume that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\). Let \(x\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) and \(U\) to be any \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set such that \(y\in U\) and \(x\in U.\) Therefore, this implies that every \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set that is containing \(y\) also contains \(x\) with \(x\neq y\) hence \(y\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}).\) Conversely, let \(U\) be \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open in \(X\) hence it implies that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exist in \(U,\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}).\) Then if \(y\) does not exist in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\})\) then \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}) \subseteq U.\) Hence it implies that both \(U\) and \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) are disjoint open sets where \(x\in U\) and \(y\) does not exists in \(U\) or \(y\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\) and \(x\) does not exist in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}).\) By Proposition 1, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}- T_{0}\) since it has topological property. Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}.\)

Proposition 6. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}\) and \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}\) if and only if it is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\) symmetric.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\) symmetric and let \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\) symmetric we need prove that it is also \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}.\) Let \(x\) and \(y\) be two disjoint closed sets in \(X.\) Then \(U\) and \(ij-\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) be any two disjoint open sets. By Definition 9, two disjoint closed sets \(x\) and \(y\) are both members of open sets either \(U\) or \(ij-\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}).\) Hence suppose that each \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set contains \(x\) and \(y\) then \(y\in U\) and \(x\in U.\) Since \(U\) is a member of \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set then it implies that \(x\in U\) and \(y\) does not exists in \(U.\) By Tychonoff theorem, it follows that \(ij-\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\})\subseteq U\) hence \(y\) does not exists \(U.\) Hence it implies that \(y\) does not exists in \(ij-\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\})\) thus by assumption \(x\) does not exists in \(ij-\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}).\) Since \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\subseteq U\) then \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}.\) Now, it implies that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\) symmetric. Therefore, every \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{\lambda}\) symmetric imply \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}- T_{0}\) we assume without any loss of generality that \(x\in K\subset X\{y\}\) for \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set \(K\) where \(x\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi _{\lambda}(\{y\})\) and \(y\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi (\{x\}).\) Therefore, \(X\setminus ij-Cl\pi(\{x\})\) is an \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set containing \(y\) but not \(x.\) Hence \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}.\)

Lemma 2. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}\) if and if for any \(x, y\in X\) and \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})= ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) then implies that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}) \cap ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})=\emptyset.\)

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}.\) Then we have disjoint closed sets \(x\) and \(y\) where \(x\in X\) such that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}) \neq ij-Cl\pi _{\lambda}(\{x\}).\) Therefore, there exists \(x\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\) such that \(x\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\})\) this implies that \(y\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\})\) and \(n\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}).\) Since \(x\) is not a member of \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\})\) therefore there exists \(V\in ij-B\lambda O (X, x)\) such that \(y\) does not exists in \(V.\) However, \(x\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\) hence \(x\in V.\) Therefore, this follows that \(x\) is not a member of \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}).\) Then it implies that \(x\in X\setminus ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}) \in ij-B\lambda O (X).\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}\) then \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\subset X\setminus ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}).\) By Proposition 6, we have \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\cap ij-\pi Cl_{\lambda}(\{y\}) = \emptyset.\) Conversely, let \(V\in ij-B\lambda O(X, x).\) We show that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\subset V.\) Let \(y\) not to be an element of \(V\) then it follows that \(y\in X\setminus V\) hence \(y=x\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}).\) This shows that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}) \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}).\) By assumption \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}) \cap ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})=\emptyset.\) By hypothesis, \(y\) does not exists in \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\) and so \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}) \subseteq V.\) Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}.\)

Theorem 1. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}\) if and only if for any points \(x\) and \(y\) in \(X,\) \(ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) =ij-Ker\pi _{\lambda} (\{y\})\) implying that \(ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \cap ij-Ker\pi _{\lambda} (\{y\}) = \emptyset.\)

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}.\) Then let disjoint closed sets \(x, y\in X.\) By hypothesis, \(ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \neq ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) then it follows that \(ij-\pi Cl_{\lambda} (\{y\}) \neq ij-\pi Cl_{\lambda}(\{x\}).\) Suppose that \(z\in ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \cap ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\})\) then it implies that \(z\in ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}).\) Therefore, it follows that \(z\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{z\}).\) Thus by Lemma 2, we have \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}) = ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{z\})\) this is by contraction. Hence \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}) = ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{z\}) = ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}).\) Therefore, \(ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\cap ij-\pi Ker_{\lambda} (\{y\}) = \emptyset.\) Conversely, let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a bitopological space such that disjoint closed points \(x\) and \(y\) are members of \(X.\) Then it implies that \(ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \neq ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) hence \(ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \cap ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}) = \emptyset.\) Therefore, \(ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) then \(\cap ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})=\emptyset.\) By assumption we have \(z\in ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\})\) and \(x\in ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) therefore \(ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \cap ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{z\}) = \emptyset.\) Therefore, \(ij- \pi Ker_{\lambda} (\{x\}) = ij-\pi Ker_{\lambda} (\{z\}).\) Thus it follows that \(z\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{x\}) = ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}).\) Then \(ij- Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) = ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{z\})= ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) this is by contradiction. Therefore, \(ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \neq ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}).\) Then this implies that \(ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}) \cap ij-Ker\pi_{\lambda}(\{y\}) = \emptyset.\) Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}.\)

Proposition 7. For bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) the following are equivalent:

  • (i). \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}.\)
  • (ii). For each \(x, y\in X\) then \(U\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{1}\)-open then \(x\in U\) if and only if \(y\in U\). \(x\in U\) and \(y\in V.\)
  • (iii). If \(x, y\in X\) such that \(ij-\pi-Cl_{\lambda}(\{x\}) \neq ij-\pi-Cl_{\lambda}(\{y\}),\) then there exists closed sets \(F_{1}\) and \(F_{2}\) whereby \(x\in F_{1},\) \(y\) does not exists in \(F_{1},\) \(y\in F_{2}\) \(x\) does not exists in \(F_{2}\) and \(X= F_{1} \cup F_{2}.\)

Proof. Proving for \((i)\Rightarrow (ii).\) Let \(x, y\) be two closed disjoint sets in \(X.\) By Theorem 1, \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\} = ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}\) or \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\} \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}.\) Let \(U\) be \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open therefore \(x\in U\) such that \(y\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}\subset U.\) Since \(x\in U\) then \(x\in ij-\pi-Cl_{\lambda} (\{y\}\subset U.\) Therefore, \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\} \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}.\) This implies that there exists disjoint \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open sets \(U\) and \(V\) such that \(x\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}\subset U\) and \(y\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}\subset V.\)

For \((ii). \Rightarrow (iii).\) Let \(x, y\in X\) such that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\} \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}.\) Since \(x\) is not a member of \( ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}\) and \(y\) is not a member of \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}\) then \(x\) does not belongs to \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\}\). Therefore, there exists \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set \(A\) such that \(x\in A\), \(y\) does not exists in \(A.\) By \((ii)\) there exists disjoints \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open sets \(U\) and \(V\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\in V.\) Then it implies that \(F_{1} = X\setminus V\) and \(F_{2} = X\setminus U\) are \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-closed sets such that \(x\in F_{1},\) \(y\) does not exists in \(F_{1},\) and \(y\in F_{2}\), \(x\) does not exists in \(F_{2}\) hence it follows that \(X= F_{1}\cap F_{2}.\)

For \((iii) \Rightarrow (i).\) We need to show that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{0}\) space. Let \(U\) be an \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set such that \(x\in U.\) Then \(ij-\pi-Cl_{\lambda} (\{x\}\subset U\) this implies that \(y\in ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\}\cap (X\setminus U).\) By (i) it implies that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{x\} \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\} = ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{y\})\) then \(y\in U.\) By \((iii),\) there exists \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-closed sets \(F_{1}\) and \(F_{2}\) such that \(x\in F_{1},\) \(y\) does not exists \(F_{1}\) but \(y\in F_{2},\) \(x\) does not exists in \(F_{2}\) such that \(X= F_{1}\cup F_{2}.\) Hence \(y\in F_{2}\setminus F_{1}\setminus X \setminus F_{1}\in ij-B\lambda O(X)\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(X\setminus F_{1}\) this is by contradiction. Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}- T_{0}\) space. Let \(p, q \in X\) such that \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{p\} \neq ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{q\},\) then there are \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-closed sets \(H_{1}\) and \(H_{2}\) such that \(p\in H_{1},\) \(q\in H_{1},\) \(q\) is not a member of \(H_{1}\) and \(q\in H_{2}\) while \(p\in H_{2}\) and \(X=H_{1}\cap H_{2}.\) Therefore, \(p\in H_{1}\setminus H_{2}\) and \(q\in H_{2}\setminus H_{1}.\) Then \(H_{1}\setminus H_{2}\) and \(H_{2}\setminus H_{1}\) are disjoint \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open sets. Hence \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda} (\{p\}) \subset H_{1} \setminus H_{2}\) and \(ij-Cl\pi_{\lambda}(\{q\}) \subset H_{2}\setminus H_{1}.\)

Theorem 2. Every normal \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}\) bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is Hausdorff space.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a normal bitopological space then we have disjoint closed sets \(x\) and \(y\) with \(x\neq y.\) Let \(U\) and \(V\) be disjoint open sets such that \(x\subset U\) and \(y\subset V.\) By Definition 24, if there exist two disjoint closed sets \(x, y \in X\) then it implies that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) is not a member of \(U\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(y\in V.\) By hypothesis, normal bitopological spaces are also \(T_{2}\) spaces. Since \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y\), then \(\exists U\in \tau_{1}\cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exists in \(U\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(y\in V.\) By Lemma 1, if \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a normal space then \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is also normal since \(A\subseteq X.\) Then there exists open disjoint sets \(U\) and \(V\) where \(U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\in V\) and \(U\cap V=\emptyset.\) Consequently, by conditions for normality it implies that \(U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) then \(U\cap A\in \tau_{A1}\) therefore, \(V\cap A\in \tau_{A2},\) and \(x\in \cap AU,\) \(y\in V\cap A.\) Then \((U\cap A) \cap (V\cap A) \cap A = \emptyset \cap A=\emptyset.\) Since \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is a bitopological subspace then it implies that it has a topological property. Let \(T_{2}\) space be Hausdorff space then we have two closed sets \(x\) and \(y\) with \(x\neq y.\) By hypothesis, we have two disjoint open sets \(U\) and \(V\) such that \(x\in U,\) \(y\) does not exists in \(V\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(y\in V\) Then it implies that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}.\) Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a Hausdorff space and every normal \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}\) space is also Hausdorff space.

Corollary 1. The property of \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}\) in bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is hereditary.

Proof. By hypothesis, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}.\) Let \(X\) be any set and \(A\subset X\) then \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is also \(T_{2}\) space. Since \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is a bitopological subspace therefore it inherits properties from \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) Let \(m, n\in A\) with \(m\neq n\) and \(m, n\in X\) with \(m \neq n.\) Then it follows that we have disjoint open sets \(U\) and \(V.\) Therefore, it implies that there exists \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(m\in U,\) \(n\) does not exists in \(V\) and \(m\) does not exists in \(V\) but \(m\in V.\) By Theorem 2, we have \(U\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}.\) This implies that \(U\in \tau_{1}\) or \(U\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(U\cap A\in \tau_{A1}\) or \(U\cap A\in \tau_{A2}.\) Hence by separation axioms it suffices that \(U\cap A\in \tau_{A1} \cap \tau_{A2}.\) Then \(m, n\in A\) and \(m\in U\cap A,\) where \(n\) is not a member of \(U\cap A\) or \(m\) is not a member of \(U\cap A,\) \(n\in U\cap A.\) Hence \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) implies \(T_{2}\) space. Since \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space then it implies that it is also \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}.\) Therefore, \((A, \tau_{A1}, \tau_{A2})\) is also \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}\) space and so it is hereditary.

Corollary 2. The property of \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}\) in bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is topological.

Proof. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2}).\) By hypothesis, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) be a homeomorphism. We have disjoint open sets \(y_{1}, y_{2}\in Y\) with \(y_{1} \neq y_{2}.\) By Definition 11, all elements in \(Y\) are images of elements in \(X\) and so \(\chi\) is a bijective function. Therefore, it implies that \(\exists x_{1} ,x_{2} \in X\) with \(\chi (x_{1}) = y_{1}\) and \(\chi(x_{2}) = y_{2}.\) Suppose \(\chi\) is a one to one function with \(y_{1} \neq y_{2}\) therefore this implies that \(\chi(x_{1}) \neq \chi(x_{2}),\) then it implies that \(x_{1} \neq x_{2}\) hence \(x_{1}, x_{2} \in X\) with \(x_{1} \neq x_{2}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space then it implies that \(\exists U\in \tau_{1}\) and \(V\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(x_{1}\in U,\) \(x_{2}\in V\) and so \(U\cap V\neq \emptyset.\) Since \(\chi\) is open hence \(\chi(U)\in \tau_{3}\) and \(\chi (V)\in \tau_{4}.\) By Tychonoff theorem, \(\chi(U)\cap \chi(V)\neq \emptyset\) suppose that there exists \(c\in X\) therefore \(c\in \chi(U) \cap \chi(V).\) This shows that \(c\in \chi(U)\) and \(c\in \chi(V)\) then \(\exists p_{1}\in U\) and \(p_{2}\in V\) such that \(c= \chi(p_{1})\) and \(c\in \chi(p_{2})\) with \(\chi(p_{1} = \chi(p_{2}).\) Suppose that \(p_{1}= p_{2}\) then it implies that \(p_{1}\in U\) and \(p_{1}\in V\) so \(p_{1}\in U\cap V\neq \emptyset.\) by contradiction if \(U\cap V= \emptyset\) then \(\chi(U) \cap \chi(V) = \emptyset.\) For any \(y_{1}, y_{2}\in Y\) with \(y_{1} \neq y_{2}\) then \(\chi(U) =\tau_{3}\) and \(\chi (V)\in c\) is obtained such that \(y_{1} \in \chi(U),\) \(y_{2} \in \chi(V)\) and \(\chi(U) \cap \chi(V)\neq \emptyset.\) Therefore, \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is a \(T_{2}\) space. Hence \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) and \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) are \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_{2}\) spaces and so they are topological.

Corollary 3. The property of \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) in bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is both topological and heredity.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space and let \(M\subseteq X.\) By hypothesis, it implies that a bitopological subspace \((M, \tau_{M1}, \tau_{M2})\) is also a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. By Proposition 4, we have \(x\in M\) with \(x\neq y.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_\frac{5}{2}\) space it implies that there exists \(A\in \tau_{1}\) and \(B\in \tau_{2}\) such that \(x\in A,\) \(y\in B\) and \(A\cap B=\emptyset\) hence it implies that \(A\in \tau_{1}\) and \(B\in \tau_{2}.\) By separation axioms technique, \(A\cap M\in \tau_{M1}\) and \(B\cap M\in \tau_{M2}\) therefore \(x, y\in M\) hence \(x\in A\cap M\) and \(y\in B\cap M.\) Then it follows that \((A\cap M)\cap (B\cap M)= (A\cap M)\cap M=\emptyset \cap M=\emptyset.\) Therefore, \((M, \tau_{M1}, \tau_{M2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is an \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) space then it has topological property. Let \(\chi: (X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\rightarrow (Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) and \(\chi\) is homeomorphic. Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) then it implies that \((Y,\tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is also an \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. By hypothesis, \(y_{1}, y_{2} \in Y\) with \(n_{1}\neq y_{2}.\) Suppose that \(\chi\) is onto function then there exists \(x_{1}, x_{2}\in X\) such that \(\chi (x_{1}) = \chi(y_{1})\) and \(\chi(y_{2}) = x_{2}.\) Also if \(\chi\) is an injective function with \(y_{1} \neq y_{2}\) it follows that \(\chi(x_{1}) \neq \chi(x_{2})\) and \(x_{1} \neq x_{2}.\) Therefore, since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) space then it implies that \(x_{1}, x_{2}\in X,\) with \(x_{1} \neq x_{2}\) and so \(\exists A\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}\) hence \(x_{1}\in A,\) \(x_{1}\) does not exists in \(A\) or \(x_{1}\) does not exists in \(A,\) \(x_{2}\in A\) similarly, \(x_{1}\in A\), \(x_{2}\) does not exists in \(A\) hence \(A\in \tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2}.\) Then \(\chi (A)\in \chi(\tau_{1} \cup \tau_{2})\) since \(\chi\) is open we have \(\chi (A) \in \chi(\tau_{1}) \cup \chi(\tau_{2})\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}.\) Since \(x_{1}\in A\) then it implies that \(\chi(x_{1})\in \chi (A)\) so \(y_{1}\in \chi(A)\) and \(x_{2}\) does not exists in \(A\) which implies that \(\chi(x_{2})\) does not exists in \(\chi(A)\) and \(y_{2}\) does not exists \(\chi(A).\) For any \(y_{1}, y_{2}\in Y\) with \(y_{1} \neq y_{2},\) \(\chi(A)\in \tau_{3} \cup \tau_{4}\) is obtained such that \(y_{1}\in \chi (A)\) and \(y_{2}\) does not exists in \(\chi(A).\) Hence \((Y, \tau_{3}, \tau_{4})\) is a \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) space. Therefore, \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-T_\frac{5}{2}\) space is both topological and hereditary.

Theorem 3. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\lambda T_{0}\) if and only if there is either closed distinct point of \(X\) either \(\tau_{1}-\eta\) or \(\tau_{2}-\eta.\)

Proof. Let \(x, y\in X\) be two distinct points in \(X.\) By hypothesis there exist two disjoint open sets \(U\) and \(V.\) Then \(U\) is a \(\tau_{1}-\eta\)-open set containing \(x\) but not \(y.\) Similarly, \(V\) is a \(\tau_{2}-\eta\)-open set that contains \(y\) but not \(x.\) Thus by Definition 17, \(y\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\subset X-U\) and so it implies that \(x\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}.\) By Proposition 7, it follows that \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl\{x\}\neq\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\) as \(x\), \(y\) are distinct points in \(X.\) Therefore \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}\neq \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\) and \(\tau_{2}-\eta cl \{x\}\neq \tau_{2}-\eta cl \{y\}.\) Suppose that \(p\) is a point of \(X\) such that \(p\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\) then \(p\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}.\) This implies that \(y\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}.\) Hence if \(y\in\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}\) then \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\subset \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}\) and \(p\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\subset \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}.\) By contradiction \(p\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}\) and so \(p\in\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\subset \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}.\) This contradicts the fact that \(p\) is not a member of \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}\) hence \(y\) also does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}.\) Therefore, \(U= X - \tau_{1}- \eta cl \{x\}\) is a \(\tau_{1}-\eta\)-open set containing \(y\) but not \(x.\) This implies that \(\tau_{2}-\eta cl \{x\}\neq \tau_{2}-\eta cl \{y\}.\) Hence \(\tau_{1}-\eta\) and \(\tau_{2}-\eta\) closures are distinct points of \(X.\)

Theorem 4. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\lambda T_{0}\) if either \((X, \tau_{1})\) or \((X, \tau_{2})\) is \(\lambda T_{0}.\)

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a bitopological space. Then \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\lambda T_{0}\) if and only if either \((X, \tau_{1})\) or \((X, \tau_{2})\) is \(\lambda T_{0}.\) By hypothesis, there are two disjoint closed sets \(x\) and \(y\) which are members of \(X.\) Similarly, there are two disjoint open sets \(U\) and \(V.\) By Theorem 3, \(U\) is a \(\tau_{1}-\eta\)-open set containing \(x\) but not \(y\) hence \(y\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\subset X-U\) and \(x\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl\{y\}.\) Since topological spaces imply bitopological spaces we have \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{x\}\neq \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{y\}\)\(\tau_{1}-\eta\) and \(\tau_{2}-\eta\) closures are distinct points. Conversely, this need not to be true in general. Let \(X= \{a, b, c\},\) \(\tau_{1} = \{X, \emptyset, \{a\}, \{b, c\}\}\) and \(\tau_{2} = \{X, \emptyset, \{c\}, \{a, b\}\}\). Therefore, it shows that a bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\lambda T_{0}\) when neither \((X, \tau_{1})\) nor is \((X, \tau_{2})\) is \(\lambda T_{0}.\)

Theorem 5. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\lambda T_{0}\) if it is normal.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a normal space. By hypothesis, it follows that there exists two disjoint closed sets \(a\) and \(b\) where \(a\neq b.\) Similarly, this implies that there exists two disjoint open sets \(M\) and \(N\) such that \(a\subset M\) and \(b\subset N.\) Then \(a, b \in X\) and so \(a\in M\) where \(a\) does not exists in \(N\) but \(b\in N\) for all \(a, b\in X\) with \(a\neq b.\) By conditions for normality, there exists \(M\in \tau_{1}\cup \tau_{2}\) such that \(a\in M,\) \(b\) does not exists in \(U\) also \(a\) does not exists in \(N\) but \(b\in N.\) This shows that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a normal space. Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(\lambda T_{0}\) then it implies that it is \(ij-\lambda T_{0}\)-normal. Thus, by Definition 18, \(M\) is a \(\tau_{1} -\eta\)-open set containing \(a\) but does not contain \(b.\) Therefore, it implies that \(b\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\}\subset X-M\) and so \(a\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\}.\) By Tychonoff theorem, we have \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}\neq \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\}.\) Since \(a\), \(b\) are two distinct points of \(X\) then neither \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}\neq \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\}\) nor \(\tau_{2}-\eta cl \{a\}\neq \tau_{2}-\eta cl \{b\}.\) Let \(c\) to be any point of \(X\) such that \(c\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\},\) \(c\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}\) and \(b\) does not belong to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}.\) If \(b\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl\{a\}\) then \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\}\subset \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}\) and \(c\in \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{b\}\subset \tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}.\) By contradiction, since \(c\) does not belongs to \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}\) then it implies that \(b\) also does not exists in \(\tau_{1}-\eta cl \{a\}\) thus \(M=X-\tau_{1}- \eta cl \{a\}\) is a \(\tau_{1}-\eta\)-open set that contains \(b\) but not \(x.\) Hence it implies that \(\tau_{2}-\eta cl \{a\}\neq \tau_{2}-\eta cl \{b\}.\) Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\lambda T_{0}\) and it implies that is a normal space.

Corollary 4. Every \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-{\lambda} T_{2}\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-\lambda T_{1}\) and \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-\lambda T_{0}.\)

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}- \lambda T_{2}.\) By hypothesis, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\lambda T_{0}.\) Let \(G\) be any \(T_{i}-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set and hence \(x\in G\) such that each point \(y\in X-G,\) \(T_{j}-\pi Cl \{y\}.\) Then it implies that there exists \(T_{i}-\pi_{\lambda}\) open set \(U_{y}\) and any \(T_{j}-\pi_{\lambda}\)-open set \(V_{y}\) such that \(x\in U_{y},\) \(y\in V_{y}.\) Therefore, by hypothesis we have \(U_{y} \cap V_{y}=\emptyset.\) If \(A=\bigcup \{V_{y}:y\in X-G\}\) then \(X-G\subset A\) and \(x\) does not exists in \(A.\) Therefore, \(T_{j}-\pi_{\lambda}\) openness of \(A\) implies that \(T_{j}-\pi Cl \{x\}\subset X-A\subset G.\) Hence \(X\) is \(\lambda T_{0}\) and \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi{\lambda}-T_{0}.\) By hypothesis, \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}- \lambda T_{0}\) and there exists closed disjoint sets \(x\) and \(y\) with \(x\neq y\) and \(x\in ij-\pi Cl_{\lambda} (\{y\}).\) By assumption \(y\) does not exists in \(ij-\pi Cl_{\lambda} (\{x\})\) then \(ij-\pi Cl_{\lambda} (\{x\})\subseteq U.\) Thus this implies that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-\lambda T_{0}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-\lambda T_{0}\) then it is \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-{\lambda} T_{2}.\) Therefore, \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-{\lambda} T_{2}\) imply \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-\lambda T_{1}\) which also imply \(ij-\pi_{\lambda}-\lambda T_{0}.\)

Proposition 8. A space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\Omega-T_{1}\) if and only if \((X, \tau_{1})\) and \((X, \tau_{2})\) are \(\Omega-T_{1}.\)

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be pairwise \(\Omega-T_{1}\) space. Let \(x\) and \(y\) be a pair of distinct points of set \(X.\) By Definition 19, there exists a \(\tau_{i}\)-preopen set which is containing \(x\) but does not contain \(y.\) Since \(x\) and \(y\) are closed sets in \(X\) then it implies that \(T_{i}-\Omega Cl\{x\} \neq T_{j}-\Omega Cl \{y\},\) \(i, j = 1, 2\) with \(i\neq j.\) Therefore, there exists a \(T_{i}-\Omega\)-open set \(U\) and a \(T_{j}-\Omega\)-open set \(V\) such that \(x\in V,\) \(y\in U\) and \(U\cap V=\emptyset.\) Therefore, it follows that \(i= 1\) or \(2\) then there exist \(\tau_{i}\)-preopen set \(U\) and \(\tau_{j}\)-preopen set \(V.\) This therefore implies that \(T_{i}-\Omega Cl \{x\}\subset V\) and \(y\in U\) implies \(T_{j}-\Omega \{y\} \subset U,\) with \(U\cap V=\emptyset\) and \(i, j = 1, 2\) where \(i\neq j\). Therefore, \((X, \tau_{1})\) and \((X, \tau_{2})\) are \(\Omega-T_{1}\) and hence \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is pairwise \(\Omega-T_{1}.\)

Theorem 6. Every bisemiopen subset of a pairwise \(p\)-regular space is pairwise \(p\)-regular.

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be pairwise \(p\)-regular space and let \(Y\subset X\) be a bisemiopen set. We show that subspace \((Y, \tau_{1Y}, \tau_{2Y})\) is pairwise \(p\)-regular. Let \(F\) be any \(\tau_{iY}\)-closed set and so \(x\) does not belongs to \(F.\) Then there exists a \(\tau_{i}\)-closed set \(A\) such that \(F= A\cap Y.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a pairwise \(p\)-regular space and \(x\in A\) then there exists \(U\in PO (X, \tau_{j})\) and \(V\in PO(X, \tau_{i})\) hence we have \(A\subset U,\) \(x\in V\) and \(U\cap V=\emptyset\) where \(i, j = 1, 2\) with \(i\neq j.\) Now, it implies that we have \(L=U\cap Y\) and \(M=V\cap Y.\) By separation axioms, it follows that \(L\in PO(X, \tau_{i})\), \(M\in PO(Y, \tau_{iY}).\) Hence \(F\subset L,\) \(x\in M\) and so it implies that the intersection of \(L\) and \(M\) is emptyset that is, \(L\cap M=\emptyset.\) Therefore, \((Y, \tau_{1Y}, \tau_{2Y})\) is pairwise \(p\)-regular space.

Theorem 7. Every quasi \(T_\frac{7}{2}\) space is quasi \(T_{0}.\)

Proof. Let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a quasi \(T_\frac{7}{2}\) space. We have \(x, y\in X\) with \(x\neq y.\) Hence it follows that \(qKer(\{x\}) \cap qKer(\{y\})=\emptyset\) since \(\{x\}\) and \(\{y\}\) are disjoint open sets with \(\{x\}\neq\{y\}.\) If \(qKer (\{x\}) \cap qKer(\{y\}) =\emptyset\) then it implies that \(T_\frac{7}{2}\) is a quasi space. Since \(\{x\}\neq \{y\}\) then by separation axioms it suffices that \(qKer (\{x\}) \neq qKer(\{y\}).\) Therefore, it implies that \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi \(T_{0}.\) Since \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi \(T_{0}\) then it is also quasi \(T_\frac{7}{2}.\)

Theorem 8. A bitopological space \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi \(T_\frac{7}{2}\) if and only if

\((qcl(\{y\}))=\cap \{y\} \bigcup(qcl(\{y\})\cap \{x\})\) is degenerate.

Proof. Let \(X\) be quasi \(T_\frac{7}{2}.\) Therefore, it shows that we have any of the two cases either \(x\) is weakly quasi separated from \(y\) or \(y\) weakly quasi separated from \(x.\) Suppose that \(x\) is weakly quasi separated from \(y\) then it implies that we have \(\{x\}\cap qcl\{y\}=\emptyset\) and \(\{y\}\cap qcl(\{x\})\) is called a degenerated set. Similarly, if \(y\) is weakly quasi separated from \(x\) then \(\{y\}\cap qcl(\{x\})=\emptyset\) and \(\{x\}\cap qcl(\{y\})\) is also a degenerated set. By Definition 29, it suffices that \((qcl(\{x\})\cap \{y\})\bigcup (qcl(\{x\})\cap \{y\})\) is a degenerate set. Hence \(qcl(\{x\})\cap \{y\})\bigcup (qcl(\{x\})\cap \{y\})\) is a degenerate set. By separation axioms, it implies that it is either an empty or singleton set. Then suppose that it is a singleton then its value is either \(\{x\}\) or \(\{y\}.\) Therefore, if it is \(\{x\}\) then \(y\) is weakly quasi separated from \(x.\) Also if it is \(\{y\}\) it is then \(x\) is weakly separated from \(y.\) Hence \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is quasi \(T_\frac{7}{2}.\)

4. Conclusion

In this paper, we have given necessary conditions and characterized separation criteria for bitopological spaces via \(ij\)-continuity. We have shown that if a bitopological space is a separation axiom space, then that separation axiom space exhibits both topological and heredity properties. For instance, let \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) be a \(T_{0}\) space then, the property of \(T_{0}\) is topological and hereditary. Similarly, when \((X, \tau_{1}, \tau_{2})\) is a \(T_{1}\) space then the property of \(T_{1}\) is topological and hereditary. Lastly, we have shown that separation axiom \(T_{0}\) implies separation axiom \(T_{1}\) which also implies separation axiom \(T_{2}\) and the converse is true.

Acknowledgments

The authors are grateful to the reviewers for their useful comments.

Author Contributions

All authors contributed equally to the writing of this paper. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Fora, A. A., & Hdeib, H. Z. (1983). On pairwise Lindelöf spaces. Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas, 17(1-2), 37-57. [Google Scholor]
  2. El-Tantawy, O. A., & Abu-Donia, H. M. (2005). Generalized separation axioms in bitopological spaces. Arabian Journal for Science and Engineering, 30(1), 117-130. [Google Scholor]
  3. Patil, P. G., & Bhat, N. N. New separation axioms in binary soft topological spaces. Italian Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics, 44, 775-783. [Google Scholor]
  4. Selvanayaki, S., & Rajesh, N. (2011). Separation axioms in bitopological spaces. International Journal of Computer Applications, 35(9), 41-44. [Google Scholor]
  5. Roshmi, R., & Hossain, M. S. (2019). Properties of Separation Axioms in Bitopological Spaces. Journal of Bangladesh Academy of Sciences, 43(2), 191-195. [Google Scholor]
  6. Kelly, J. (1963). Bitopological spaces. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 3(1), 71-89. [Google Scholor]
  7. Ivanov, A. A. (1984). Bitopological spaces. Journal of Soviet Mathematics, 26(1), 1622-1636. [Google Scholor]
  8. McCoy, R. A., & Ntantu, I. (2006). Topological Properties of Spaces of Continuous Functions (Vol. 1315). Springer.[Google Scholor]
  9. Noiri, T., & Popa, V. (2006). Some properties of weakly open functions in bitopological spaces. Novi Sad Journal of Mathematics, 36(1), 47-54. [Google Scholor]
  10. Orihuela, J. (2007). Topological open problems in the geometry of Banach spaces. Extracta Mathematicae, 22(2), 197-213. [Google Scholor]
  11. Kohli, J. K., & Singh, D. (2010). Between strong continuity and almost continuity. Applied General Fopology, 11(1), 29-42. [Google Scholor]
  12. Caldas, M. (2008). Study of Some Topological Concepts in Bitopological Spaces. Journal of Kerbala University, 6, 23-27. [Google Scholor]
  13. Birman, C. C. (2018). Continuity in Topological Spaces. Amazon. [Google Scholor]
  14. Sidney, A. M. (2012). Topology Without Tears. Springer Verlag, New York. [Google Scholor]
  15. Sasikala, D. (2013). \((1,2)\)-j-open sets in Bitopological spaces. Journal of Academia and Industrial Research, 1, 3-18. [Google Scholor]
  16. Chodounský, D., & Murtinová, E. (2008). Internal normality and internal compactness. Topology and its Applications, 155(4), 201-206. [Google Scholor]
  17. Ittanagi, B. M. (2014). Soft bitopological spaces. International Journal of Computer Applications, 107(7), 1-4. [Google Scholor]
  18. Tallafha, A., Al-Bsoul, A., & FORA, A. A. (2000). Countable dense homogeneous Bitopological spaces. Turkish Journal of Mathematics, 23(2), 233-242. [Google Scholor]
  19. Kiliçman, A., & Salleh, Z. (2007). Mappings and pairwise continuity on pairwise Lindelöf bitopological spaces, Albanian Journal of Mathematics, 1(2), 115-120. [Google Scholor]
  20. Thivagar, M. L., Ramesh, V., & Dasan, M. A. (2016). On new structure of N-topology. Cogent Mathematics, 3(1), 1204104. [Google Scholor]
  21. Nada, M. A. (2011). The Connected and Continuity in Bitopological Spaces. For Pure Sciences Babylon University. [Google Scholor]
  22. Fathi, H. K.(2007). Pairwise set and pairwise continuity in Bitopological spaces. Mathematics Department, Fuculty of Sciences, Assiut University Egypt, 36(2), 19-34. [Google Scholor]
  23. Bhattacharya B. (2014). Open Sets in Bitopoplogical Spaces. RIMS, Kyoto University. [Google Scholor]
  24. Khedr F. H., & Albowi S. A. (1992). \(c\alpha\)-continuity in Bitopological Spaces. Mathematics Department, Fuculty of Sciences, Assuit University Egypt 15,(3), 17-20. [Google Scholor]
  25. Pious, S. M., & Anbarasi R. P. (2014). Strongly \(\alpha^{\ast}\) continuous functions in Topological spaces. IOSR Journal of Mathematics, 10(4), 55-60. [Google Scholor]
  26. Schapira, P. (2010). General Topology. Course at Paris VI University, 3. [Google Scholor]
  27. Saegrove, M. J. (1971). On Bitopological Spaces. Iowa State University. [Google Scholor]
  28. Samer, A., & Bayan I. (2020). On \(\theta_{\omega}\) continuity. Heliyon, 6, e03349. [Google Scholor]
  29. Kim, J. T., & Lee, S. J. (2019). Pairwise precontinuity in intuitionistic smooth bitopological spaces. International Journal of Fuzzy Logic and Intelligent Systems, 19(3), 204-212. [Google Scholor]
  30. Sunganya, R., & Rajesh, N. (2015). Separation axioms in Bitopological spaces. International Journal of Innovative Science, Engineering and Technology, 2(11), 857-866. [Google Scholor]
  31. Arya, S. P., & Nour, T. M. (1988). Separation axioms for Bitopological spaces. Indian Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics, 19(1), 42-50. [Google Scholor]
  32. Kocinac, L. D., & Özçag, S. (2011). Versions of separability in Bitopological spaces. Topology and its Applications, 158(12), 1471-1477. [Google Scholor]
  33. Al-Hawary, T. A., & Al-Omari, A. (2012). Quasi b-open sets in Bitopological spaces. Abhath AL-Yarmouk Journal, 21, 1-14. [Google Scholor]
  34. Alblowi, S. A. (2014). Relative Continuity and New Decompositions of Continuity in Bitopological Spaces. International Journal of Modern Nonlinear Theory and Application, 3(5), 248-255. [Google Scholor]
  35. Pawar, A. Contra pairwise continuity in Bitopological spaces. International journal of Mathematics and Statistics Invention, 1(2), 41-55. [Google Scholor]
  36. Kumar Banerjee, A., & Kumar Saha, P. (2015). Semi open sets in bispaces. Cubo (Temuco), 17(1), 99-106. [Google Scholor]
  37. Nour, T. M. (1995). A note on five separation axioms in Bitopological spaces. Indian Journal Of Pure And Applied Mathematics, 26, 669-674. [Google Scholor]
  38. Salleh, Z., & Kiliçman, A. (2013). On pairwise nearly Lindelöf Bitopological spaces. Far East Journal of Mathematical Sciences, 77(2), 147. [Google Scholor]
  39. Shakhmatov, D., & Spevák, J. (2010). Group-valued continuous functions with the topology of pointwise convergence. Topology and its Applications, 157(8), 1518-1540. [Google Scholor]
  40. Beshimov, R. B. (2002). A note on weakly separable spaces. Mathematica Moravica, (6), 9-19. [Google Scholor]
  41. Maji, P. K., Roy, A. R., & Biswas, R. (2002). An application of soft sets in a decision making problem. Computers & Mathematics with Applications, 44(8-9), 1077-1083. [Google Scholor]